Aristotle, Eleaticism, and Zeno’s Grains of Millet
PDF

Keywords

Aristotle
Eleaticism
Parmenides
Zeno
motion
mathematical proportions

How to Cite

Boeri, M. D. (2021) “Aristotle, Eleaticism, and Zeno’s Grains of Millet”, Peitho. Examina Antiqua, 12(1), pp. 107–122. doi: 10.14746/pea.2021.1.6.

Abstract

This paper explores how Aristotle rejects some Eleatic tenets in general and some of Zeno’s views in particular that apparently threaten the Aristotelian “science of nature.” According to Zeno, it is impossible for a thing to traverse what is infinite or to come in contact with infinite things in a finite time. Aristotle takes the Zenonian view to be wrong by resorting to his distinction between potentiality and actuality and to his theory of mathematical proportions as applied to the motive power and the moved object (Ph. VII.5). He states that some minimal parts of certain magnitudes (i.e., continuous quantities) are perceived, but only in potentiality, not in actuality. This being so, Zeno’s view that a single grain of millet makes no sound on falling, but a thousand grains make a sound must be rejected. If Zeno’s paradoxes were true, there would be no motion, but if there is no motion, there is no nature, and hence, there cannot be a science of nature. What Aristotle noted in the millet seed paradox, I hold, is that it apparently casts doubt on his theory of mathematical proportions, i.e., the theory of proportions that holds between the moving power and the object moved, and the extent of the change and the time taken. This approach explains why Aristotle establishes an analogy between the millet seed paradox, on the one hand, and the argument of the stone being worn away by the drop of water (Ph. 253b15–16) and the hauled ship, on the other.

https://doi.org/10.14746/pea.2021.1.6
PDF

References

Barnes, J., 1982, The Presocratic Philosophers, London—New York.

Barnes, J., 2012, “Medicine, experience and logic”, in: J. Barnes, Logical Matters. Essays in Ancient Philosophy II, M. Bonelli (ed.), Oxford, pp. 538–581.

Berryman, S., 2019, The Mechanical Hypothesis in Ancient Greek Natural Philosophy, Cambridge.

Bolotin, D., 1998, An Approach to Aristotle’s Physics with Particular Attention to the Role of His Manner of Writing, New York.

Booth, N. B., 1957, “Were Zeno’s Arguments a Reply to Attacks upon Parmenides?”, Phronesis 2 (1), pp. 1–9.

Cordero, N. L., 2004, By Being it is. The Thesis of Parmenides, Las Vegas.

Curd, P., 2004, The Legacy of Parmenides. Eleatic Monism and Later Presocratic Thought, Las Vegas.

De Groot, J., 2014, Aristotle’s Empiricism. Experience and Mechanics in the Fourth Century BC, Las Vegas—Zürich—Athens.

Kirk, G. S., Raven, J. E., Schofield, M., 1991, The Presocratic Philosophers. A Critical History with a Selection of Texts, Cambridge.

Mortensen, C., 2007, “Zeno’s Paradoxes”, in: E. Close, M. Tsianikas, G. Couvalis (eds.), Greek Research in Australia: Proceedings of the Sixth Biennial International Conference of Greek Studies, Adelaide, pp. 11–18.

Owen, G. E. L., 1986a, “Aristotelian Mechanics”, in: G.E.L. Owen, Logic, Science and Dialectic. Collected Papers in Greek Philosophy, M. Nussbaum (ed.), Ithaca—New York, pp. 315–333.

Owen, G. E. L., 1986b, “Aristotle: Method, Physics and Cosmology”, in: G.E.L. Owen, Logic, Science and Dialectic. Collected Papers in Greek Philosophy, M. Nussbaum (ed.), Ithaca—New York, pp. 151–164.

Rovelli, C., 2015, “Aristotle’s Physics – A Physicist’s Look”, Journal of the American Philosophical Association 1, pp. 23–40.

Sambursky, S., 1962, The Physical World of Late Antiquity, Princeton.

Tood, R. E. (transl.), 2008, Themistius, On Aristotle, Physics 5–8, London—New Dehli—New York—Sydney.

Treder, H. J., 1988, “Aristote et la physique”, in: M. A. Sinaceur (ed.), Aristote Aujourd’hui. Études réunies à l’occasion du 2300e anniversaire de la mort du philosophe, Paris-Toulouse, pp.113–122.

Wardy, R., 1990, The Chain of Change. A Study of Aristotle’s Physics VII, Cambridge.